Originally
published as a pamphlet with the title 'Contre le fonctionalisme', Paris
(1957). Translated by Thomas Y.Levin and taken from Situationist International
Online
|
On the Current Value of the Functionalist Idea
Asger Jorn
The last few years have witnessed an ever-growing dissatisfaction with
rationalist ideas of functionalism. One speaks increasingly of a revolution
against its unsupportable constraints, and this revolution seems inevitable
and obvious. But before throwing everything onto the scrap heap, it is
worth reflecting on the nature of a true revolution, because the latter
cannot come into being by destroying things willy-nilly.
We must preserve what to us seems workable within the heritage of functionalism.
As soon as the latter set itself against the old classicism, it proclaimed
that "the house is a machine for living in," "the kitchen is a machine
for feeding," etc. These arguments triumphed by virtue of their indubitable
truth.
The functionalists made a rational analysis of structure and its functions;
they reduced form to its most economic aspect for the satisfaction of
our needs. Thus, they created a hitherto unknown understanding of the
object and the implement. Over and above this objective functionalism,
they aspired to a humanist analysis of the social and ethical functions
of our environment, with its unfolding on a democratic base, underpinned
by a "concept of urbanism" that ordains man's right to a domicile that
ensures him a salubrious and calm existence.
In laying the foundations of an irrational architecture, it would be
inconceivable to omit these vitally important facts. It is easy and doubtless
amusing to create new ideas in opposition to old ones, but culture is
the opposite of this: it is the elaboration and continuous transformation
of already-existing pheenomena. The functionalist slogan can always be
of use to us. Usefulness and function remain the point of departure for
any formal critique; it is simply a question of transforming the functionalist
program. It is always worthwhile to try to arrive at the most effective
result by the economic means. But if we agreed on this point, why then
do we claim to be dissatisfied with functionalsim? It is because of its
aesthetic, which never sought to regard the aesthetic aspect as an autonomous
function of human activity. Aesthetics is "the science of the beautiful
and the ugly." Following Platonism, the functionalists contrived to deny
the autonomous existence of beauty by saying that "what is true and good
is always beautiful": namely, that logic and ethics have beauty already
built into them.
By dint of this false notion, they constructed an aethetic idea that
consists in the constructivist idea and in seeing the outside of the object
as a reflection of the practical functions of its inside. Nevertheless,
these analyses of usefulness and necessity, which, according to their
lights, must be the basis for the construction of any object created by
man, are immediately rendered ridiculous if one analyzes all objects manufactured
today. A fork or a bed cannot come to be considered as necessary for the
life and health of man and still retain a relative value.
It is a question of "acquired necessities." Modern man is smothered
in these necessities - the television, the fridge, etc. - that render
him incapable of living his real life. Obviously, we are not opposed to
modern technology, but we are against any idea of the absolute necessity
of objects, going so far as to doubt their effective usefulness.
Moreover, the functionalists ignore the psychological function of the
environment. Just as coffee has no value for the health of man but only
a psychological and sensory importance, so the sight of the outside of
the buildings and objects that surround us and that we use has a function
independent of their practical usefulness. The outside of a house ought
not to reflect the inside but constitute a source of poetic sensation
for the observer.
|
|